Unleash the Power of Countability: How to Tame Infinite Sets with a Simple List

Here’s a persuasive advertisement for ghostwriting services specifically for the theme of “Proving the Countability of a Union of Countable Sets”:

**Get Expert Help with Proving Countability**

Stuck with proving the countability of a union of countable sets? Our expert ghostwriters can help!

**Our Services:**

* Customized solutions for listing elements and using a systematic counting method
* Well-structured and logically sound proofs
* Clear and concise explanations for easy understanding
* 100% original and plagiarism-free content

**Why Choose Us:**

* Our team of experienced mathematicians and writers have a deep understanding of set theory and counting principles
* Fast turnaround times without compromising on quality
* Confidential and secure services to ensure your academic integrity
* Affordable prices without breaking the bank

**Let Us Take Care of Your Proofs**

Don’t let the complexity of countability proofs hold you back. Our ghostwriting services will help you achieve academic success with ease. Order now and get a well-crafted proof that will impress your instructors!

countable. The fact that it is a countable union means we are allowed to write out sets in a list

\[X_{1},X_{1},X_{3},\ldots\]

and then the fact that each \(X_{n}\) is countable allow us to list its elements as \(x_{n1},x_{n2},x_{n3},\ldots\). We then finish the proof showing some systematic way of counting through \(x_{nm}\). In this proof we made an infinite number of unspecified choices; we “choose” a list of elements of \(X_{n}\) without specifying the choice we had made. Moreover since we know nothing about the sets \(X_{n}\), it is impossible to say how we list them. For a long time mathematicians discussed among themselves about the use of the axiom of choice and seemingly contradictory results it produced. Why do people make a fuss about the axiom of choice? The main reason is that if it is used in a proof, then the part of that proof is nonconstructive. Now most seem to agree that the advantages of the axiom of choice outweigh the disadvantages.

**Definition 5**.: Suppose \(X\) is a set, \(I\) is an index set (not assumed to be countable), and \(\{X_{i}\}_{i\in I}\) is a collection of nonempty subsets of \(X\). We call \(\psi\) a _choice function_ if \(\psi:I\to\bigcup_{i\in I}X_{i}\), defined as \(i\mapsto x_{i}\) such that \(\psi(i)\in X_{i}\) for all \(i\). The axiom of choice can be stated as follows:

**The Axiom of Choice:** For every collection of nonempty sets, there exists a choice function.

Note that the axiom of choice is a nonconstructive assertion of existence. It postulates the existence of certain objects without giving any indication of how to find these objects. There are various logically equivalent statements to the axiom of choice, such as the Hausdorff Principle, Zorn’s lemma, and Well-Ordering Principle which we state below. Among these are two forms of the axiom of choice that are more often used in mathematics than the basic form we stated above. One is the _well-ordering principle_ which states every set can be well-ordered. The other is _Zorn’s lemma_ which states under certain circumstances “maximal” element exists. This is hugely important; for example, a basis for a vector space is precisely a maximal linearly independent set, and it turns out that Zorn’s lemma applies to collections of linearly independent sets in a vector space, which shows that every vector space has a basis.

To define these equivalent concepts, we first need the definitions of _partially ordered set_, _totally ordered set_, and _well-ordered set_.

**Definition 6**.: A _partially ordered set_ is a set \(X\) with a relation \(\leq\) that is reflexive, transitive, and antisymmetric. By antisymmetric we mean if \(x\leq y\) and \(y\leq x\), then \(x=y\). In a partially ordered set, an element \(y\) is _maximal_ if \(x\geq y\) implies \(x=y\). Also, in a partially ordered set \(X\) with \(Y\subset X\), an _upper bound_ for \(Y\) is an element \(x\in X\) such that \(y\leq x\) for all \(y\in Y\).

A _totally ordered set_ is a partially ordered set with an additional property that for any two elements, say \(x,y\in X\) (\(x\) and \(y\) distinct), either \(x\leq y\) or \(y\leq x\) (but not both). Finally, a _well-ordered set_\(X\) is a totally ordered set in which any nonempty subset \(E\subset X\) has a least element. That is an element \(x^{*}\in E\) such that \(x^{*}\leq x\) for any other \(x\in E\).

**Example 14**.: Simple examples of totally ordered sets are \((\mathbb{N},\leq)\), \((\mathbb{Q},\leq)\), and \((\mathbb{R},\leq)\). Let \(X\) be a set, and let \(\mathcal{P}(X)\) denote the collection of all subsets of \(X\). Then it is not hard to see that \((\mathcal{P}(X),\subseteq)\) is a partially ordered set.

**Hausdorff Maximality Principle:** Every partially ordered set \(X\) contains a totally ordered subset \(Y\) that is maximal with respect to the ordering on \(\mathcal{P}(X)\).

**Zorn’s Lemma:** If a nonempty partially ordered set has the property that every nonempty totally ordered subset has an upper bound, then the partially ordered set has a maximal element.

**Well-Ordering Principle:** Any set \(X\) can be well-ordered.

Perhaps it is obvious that the Well-Ordering Principle implies the Axiom of Choice, because if we well-order \(X\), we can choose \(x_{i}\) to be the smallest element of \(X_{i}\), and in this way we have constructed the required choice function. However, it is not so easy to show that the Axiom of Choice implies the Well-Ordering Principle. The proofs of the equivalence of the Axiom of Choice, the Hausdorff Maximality Principle, Zorn’s lemma, and the Well-Ordering Principle are all explained in the book by Paul J. Sally [43], p. 40.

We will need the axiom of choice in Sections 2.7 and 2.8 of Chapter 2, when we are discussing non-measurable sets and the proof of the Banach-Tarski paradox. The Banach-Tarski paradox states that there is a way of dividing a solid unit sphere into a finite number of subsets and then reassembling these subsets using rotations, reflections, and translations to form two solid unit spheres. The proof does not provide an explicit way of defining subsets. Why does it seem strange and paradoxical? It is because we feel volume has not been preserved. But how do we know we can give a sensible definition of volume for all subsets of the sphere? This leads us to measure theory and non-measurable sets.

### Exercises

1. For two sets \(A\) and \(B\), show that the following statements are equivalent:

1. \(A\subseteq B\).
2. \(A\cup B=B\).
3. \(A\cap B=A\).

2. Establish the following set theoretic relations:1. \(A\cup B=B\cup A\) and \(A\cap B=B\cap A\) (Commutativity).
2. \(A\cup(B\cup C)=(A\cup B)\cup C\) and \(A\cap(B\cap C)=(A\cap B)\cap C\) (Associativity).
3. \(A\cup(B\cap C)=(A\cup B)\cap(B\cup C)\) and \(A\cap(B\cup C)=(A\cap B)\cup(B\cap C)\) (Distributivity).
4. \(A\subseteq B\iff B^{c}\subseteq A^{c}\).
5. \(A\setminus B=A\cap B^{c}\).
6. \((A\cup B)^{c}=A^{c}\cap B^{c}\) and \((A\cap B)^{c}=A^{c}\cup B^{c}\). (De Morgan’s laws).
7. If \(A,B\), and \(C\) are sets, show that 1. \(A\times B=\emptyset\iff A=\emptyset\) or \(B=\emptyset\).
8. \((A\cup B)\times C=(A\times C)\cup(B\times C)\).
9. \((A\cap B)\times C=(A\times C)\cap(B\times C)\).
10. Suppose \(f:A\to B\) and \(g:B\to C\) are functions, show that 1. If both \(f\) and \(g\) are one-to-one, then \(g\circ f\) is one-to-one.
11. If both \(f\) and \(g\) are onto, then \(g\circ f\) is onto.
12. If both \(f\) and \(g\) are bijection, then \(g\circ f\) is a bijection.
13. For an arbitrary function \(f:X\to Y\), prove that the following relations hold: 1. \(f(\bigcup_{i\in I}A_{i})=\bigcup_{i\in I}f(A_{i})\). 2. \(f(\bigcap_{i\in I}A_{i})\subseteq\bigcap_{i\in I}f(A_{i})\). 3. Give a counterexample to show that \(f(\bigcap_{i\in I}A_{i})=\bigcap_{i\in I}f(A_{i})\) is not always true.
14. Given \(f:A\to B\), suppose there exists two functions \(g:B\to A\) and \(h:B\to A\) such that \(f\circ g=I_{B}\) and \(h\circ f=I_{A}\). Show that \(f\) is a bijection and that \(f^{-1}=g=h\).
15. For a function \(f:X\longrightarrow Y\), show that the following statements are equivalent: 1. \(f\) is one-to-one. 2. \(f\left(A\cap B\right)=f\left(A\right)\cap f\left(B\right)\) holds for all \(A,B\in\mathcal{P}\left(X\right)\).

8. Let \(A\) be a set, and let \(\mathcal{P}(A)\) denote the set of all subsets of \(A\) (i.e., the power set of \(A\)). Prove that \(A\) and \(\mathcal{P}(A)\) do not have the same cardinality.

9. If \(A\) and \(B\) are sets, then show that

1. \(\mathcal{P}(A)\cup\mathcal{P}(B)\subseteq\mathcal{P}(A\cup B)\).
2. \(\mathcal{P}(A)\cap\mathcal{P}(B)=\mathcal{P}(A\cap B)\).

10. Prove \((1+x)^{n}\geq 1+nx\) for all real \(x>-1\) and all positive integers \(n\) (_Bernoulli’s inequality_).

11. Prove \(2^{n}\geq n^{2}\) for all \(n\geq 4\).

12. An _algebraic number_ is a root of a polynomial whose coefficients are rational. Show that the set of all algebraic numbers is countable.

13. Show that a countable union of finite or countable sets is countable.

14. Show that \((0,1)\) is uncountable if and only if \(\mathbb{R}\) is uncountable.

15. Let \(X=\mathbb{R}^{2}\), and define \(\vec{u}\sim\vec{v}\) if \(\vec{u}-\vec{v}\in\mathbb{Z}^{2}\), i.e., two vectors in the plane are equivalent if their components differ by integers. Then show that \(\sim\) is an equivalence relation.

### 1.2 Number Systems

For most of us, our first exposure to mathematical reasoning involves numbers and computation, and sadly too many of us never encounter any mathematics past this early stage. Even worse, the interesting aspects of numbers are too often ignored in favor of mechanical algorithms for computation. In this section we will explore the various number systems that are used throughout mathematics. We will focus on the interesting side too often ignored in favor of the mechanics of computation, which we assume the reader is familiar with from high school algebra.

### The Natural Numbers

Recalling the definition given in Example 7, the _natural numbers_

\[\mathbb{N}=\{1,2,3,\dots,n,\dots\}\]

are the kinds of numbers, which can be cardinalities of finite sets. Indeed, this is how we first conceptualize natural numbers – to teach a child the concept of the number two, we might show him her many examples of pairs of things.

Thinking of the natural numbers as cardinalities of finite sets gives us two operations on \(\mathbb{N}\): _addition_ comes from taking unions of disjoint sets, and _multiplication_ comes from taking Cartesian products:

\[|A|+|B|=|A\cup B|\quad(\text{if }A\cap B=\emptyset)\quad\text{and}\quad|A|\times|B|=|A \times B|.\]

In order to minimize writing, we generally omit the “\(\times\)” symbol when multiplying, writing “\(xy\)” instead of “\(x\times y\).”

These operations of addition and multiplication have some important properties:

* **Commutativity.** If we are adding or multiplying two natural numbers, the order of the two numbers does not matter: \[x+y=y+x\quad\text{and}\quad xy=yx.\]
* **Associativity.** If we are adding or multiplying three numbers, it does not matter what order we resolve the operations: \[x+(y+z)=(x+y)+z\quad\text{and}\quad x(yz)=(xy)z.\]
* **Identity Elements.** There are natural numbers \(0\) and \(1\) which are _identity elements_ with respect to addition and multiplication, respectively: \[0+x=x\quad\text{and}\quad 1x=x.\]

Not every operation on a set has the properties above; they are useful enough that mathematicians have a name for a set with an operation satisfying all the properties above. A set with an associative operation is called a _semigroup_; a semigroup with an identity element is called a _monoid_, and if the operation is commutative, we have a _commutative semigroup_ or _commutative monoid_.

### The Integers and Rational Numbers

As someone playing with sets quickly observes, some additions and multiplications can be undone, while others cannot – we can undo multiplication by two if our input is even, but not if it is odd.

One approach is to define new operations that undo the old ones, e.g., subtraction and division. However, there are some problems (or at least, inelegancies) in this approach – the “undoing operations” may not share the nice properties of the operation they undo, and worse, they may not even make sense at all in some cases.

For example, subtraction and division are both non-commutative and non-associative:

\[3-2\neq 2-3\quad\text{and}\quad 2\div 3\neq 3\div 2,\]

while

\[1-(2-3)=1-(-1)=2\neq-4=-1-3=(1-2)-3\]and

\[1\div(2\div 3)=\frac{3}{2}\neq\frac{1}{6}=(1\div 2)\div 3.\]

More problematic is the fact that the operation may not even be defined for every pair of natural numbers. For example, division by zero does not make any sense – if \(x\div 0=y\), then \(0y=x\), which is not possible if \(x\) and \(y\) are both nonzero natural numbers.

A better solution is to expand the set of numbers we are using so that we can undo addition with another addition. That is, for every natural number \(x\neq 0\), we would like there to be another number \(-x\) such that \(-x+x=0\) and a number \(x^{-1}\) such that \(xx^{-1}=1\). Including these gives us the _negative integers_ and _rational numbers_, respectively. In particular, subtraction \(x-y\) is simply addition to \(x\) of \(-y\) and division \(x\div y\) is simply multiplication of \(x\) by \(y^{-1}\). The numbers \(-x\) and \(x^{-1}\) are the _additive inverse_ and _multiplicative inverse_, respectively, of \(x\).

diagram

评论

发表回复

您的电子邮箱地址不会被公开。 必填项已用 * 标注